Katana VentraIP

Axiom of choice

In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of sets, each containing at least one element, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from each set, even if the collection is infinite. Formally, it states that for every indexed family of nonempty sets, there exists an indexed set such that for every . The axiom of choice was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo in order to formalize his proof of the well-ordering theorem.[1]

This article is about the mathematical concept. For the band, see Axiom of Choice (band).

In many cases, a set created by choosing elements can be made without invoking the axiom of choice, particularly if the number of sets from which to choose the elements is finite, or if a canonical rule on how to choose the elements is available — some distinguishing property that happens to hold for exactly one element in each set. An illustrative example is sets picked from the natural numbers. From such sets, one may always select the smallest number, e.g. given the sets {{4, 5, 6}, {10, 12}, {1, 400, 617, 8000}}, the set containing each smallest element is {4, 10, 1}. In this case, "select the smallest number" is a choice function. Even if infinitely many sets are collected from the natural numbers, it will always be possible to choose the smallest element from each set to produce a set. That is, the choice function provides the set of chosen elements. But no definite choice function is known for the collection of all non-empty subsets of the real numbers. In that case, the axiom of choice must be invoked.


Bertrand Russell coined an analogy: for any (even infinite) collection of pairs of shoes, one can pick out the left shoe from each pair to obtain an appropriate collection (i.e. set) of shoes; this makes it possible to define a choice function directly. For an infinite collection of pairs of socks (assumed to have no distinguishing features), there is no obvious way to make a function that forms a set out of selecting one sock from each pair without invoking the axiom of choice.[2]


Although originally controversial, the axiom of choice is now used without reservation by most mathematicians,[3] and is included in the standard form of axiomatic set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC). One motivation for this is that a number of generally accepted mathematical results, such as Tychonoff's theorem, require the axiom of choice for their proofs. Contemporary set theorists also study axioms that are not compatible with the axiom of choice, such as the axiom of determinacy. The axiom of choice is avoided in some varieties of constructive mathematics, although there are varieties of constructive mathematics in which the axiom of choice is embraced.

Katana VentraIP

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#0__titleDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#0__subtitleDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#0__call_to_action.textDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

AC – the Axiom of Choice. More rarely, AoC is used.

[4]

ZF – omitting the Axiom of Choice.

Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory

ZFC – Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, extended to include the Axiom of Choice.

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#1__titleDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#1__descriptionDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

Usage[edit]

Until the late 19th century, the axiom of choice was often used implicitly, although it had not yet been formally stated. For example, after having established that the set X contains only non-empty sets, a mathematician might have said "let F(s) be one of the members of s for all s in X" to define a function F. In general, it is impossible to prove that F exists without the axiom of choice, but this seems to have gone unnoticed until Zermelo.

Examples[edit]

The nature of the individual nonempty sets in the collection may make it possible to avoid the axiom of choice even for certain infinite collections. For example, suppose that each member of the collection X is a nonempty subset of the natural numbers. Every such subset has a smallest element, so to specify our choice function we can simply say that it maps each set to the least element of that set. This gives us a definite choice of an element from each set, and makes it unnecessary to add the axiom of choice to our axioms of set theory.


The difficulty appears when there is no natural choice of elements from each set. If we cannot make explicit choices, how do we know that our selection forms a legitimate set (as defined by the other ZF axioms of set theory)? For example, suppose that X is the set of all non-empty subsets of the real numbers. First we might try to proceed as if X were finite. If we try to choose an element from each set, then, because X is infinite, our choice procedure will never come to an end, and consequently we shall never be able to produce a choice function for all of X. Next we might try specifying the least element from each set. But some subsets of the real numbers do not have least elements. For example, the open interval (0,1) does not have a least element: if x is in (0,1), then so is x/2, and x/2 is always strictly smaller than x. So this attempt also fails.


Additionally, consider for instance the unit circle S, and the action on S by a group G consisting of all rational rotations, that is, rotations by angles which are rational multiples of π. Here G is countable while S is uncountable. Hence S breaks up into uncountably many orbits under G. Using the axiom of choice, we could pick a single point from each orbit, obtaining an uncountable subset X of S with the property that all of its translates by G are disjoint from X. The set of those translates partitions the circle into a countable collection of disjoint sets, which are all pairwise congruent. Since X is not measurable for any rotation-invariant countably additive finite measure on S, finding an algorithm to form a set from selecting a point in each orbit requires that one add the axiom of choice to our axioms of set theory. See non-measurable set for more details.


In classical arithmetic, the natural numbers are well-ordered: for every nonempty subset of the natural numbers, there is a unique least element under the natural ordering. In this way, one may specify a set from any given subset. One might say, "Even though the usual ordering of the real numbers does not work, it may be possible to find a different ordering of the real numbers which is a well-ordering. Then our choice function can choose the least element of every set under our unusual ordering." The problem then becomes that of constructing a well-ordering, which turns out to require the axiom of choice for its existence; every set can be well-ordered if and only if the axiom of choice holds.

Criticism and acceptance[edit]

A proof requiring the axiom of choice may establish the existence of an object without explicitly defining the object in the language of set theory. For example, while the axiom of choice implies that there is a well-ordering of the real numbers, there are models of set theory with the axiom of choice in which no individual well-ordering of the reals is definable. Similarly, although a subset of the real numbers that is not Lebesgue measurable can be proved to exist using the axiom of choice, it is consistent that no such set is definable.[8]


The axiom of choice proves the existence of these intangibles (objects that are proved to exist, but which cannot be explicitly constructed), which may conflict with some philosophical principles.[9] Because there is no canonical well-ordering of all sets, a construction that relies on a well-ordering may not produce a canonical result, even if a canonical result is desired (as is often the case in category theory). This has been used as an argument against the use of the axiom of choice.


Another argument against the axiom of choice is that it implies the existence of objects that may seem counterintuitive.[10] One example is the Banach–Tarski paradox, which says that it is possible to decompose the 3-dimensional solid unit ball into finitely many pieces and, using only rotations and translations, reassemble the pieces into two solid balls each with the same volume as the original. The pieces in this decomposition, constructed using the axiom of choice, are non-measurable sets.


Moreover, paradoxical consequences of the axiom of choice for the no-signaling principle in physics have recently been pointed out.[11]


Despite these seemingly paradoxical results, most mathematicians accept the axiom of choice as a valid principle for proving new results in mathematics. But the debate is interesting enough that it is considered notable when a theorem in ZFC (ZF plus AC) is logically equivalent (with just the ZF axioms) to the axiom of choice, and mathematicians look for results that require the axiom of choice to be false, though this type of deduction is less common than the type that requires the axiom of choice to be true.


Theorems of ZF hold true in any model of that theory, regardless of the truth or falsity of the axiom of choice in that particular model. The implications of choice below, including weaker versions of the axiom itself, are listed because they are not theorems of ZF. The Banach–Tarski paradox, for example, is neither provable nor disprovable from ZF alone: it is impossible to construct the required decomposition of the unit ball in ZF, but also impossible to prove there is no such decomposition. Such statements can be rephrased as conditional statements—for example, "If AC holds, then the decomposition in the Banach–Tarski paradox exists." Such conditional statements are provable in ZF when the original statements are provable from ZF and the axiom of choice.

Stronger axioms[edit]

The axiom of constructibility and the generalized continuum hypothesis each imply the axiom of choice and so are strictly stronger than it. In class theories such as Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory and Morse–Kelley set theory, there is an axiom called the axiom of global choice that is stronger than the axiom of choice for sets because it also applies to proper classes. The axiom of global choice follows from the axiom of limitation of size. Tarski's axiom, which is used in Tarski–Grothendieck set theory and states (in the vernacular) that every set belongs to some Grothendieck universe, is stronger than the axiom of choice.

Set theory

Tarski's theorem about choice

Abstract algebra

vector space

Functional analysis

normed vector space

Point-set topology

Cartesian product

Mathematical logic

first-order logic

Graph theory

connected graph

Set theory

ultrafilter lemma

Measure theory

Vitali theorem

Algebra

field

Functional analysis

Hahn–Banach theorem

General topology

Tychonoff space

Mathematical logic

Gödel's completeness theorem

Stronger forms of the negation of AC[edit]

If we abbreviate by BP the claim that every set of real numbers has the property of Baire, then BP is stronger than ¬AC, which asserts the nonexistence of any choice function on perhaps only a single set of nonempty sets. Strengthened negations may be compatible with weakened forms of AC. For example, ZF + DC[35] + BP is consistent, if ZF is.


It is also consistent with ZF + DC that every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable, but this consistency result, due to Robert M. Solovay, cannot be proved in ZFC itself, but requires a mild large cardinal assumption (the existence of an inaccessible cardinal). The much stronger axiom of determinacy, or AD, implies that every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable, has the property of Baire, and has the perfect set property (all three of these results are refuted by AC itself). ZF + DC + AD is consistent provided that a sufficiently strong large cardinal axiom is consistent (the existence of infinitely many Woodin cardinals).


Quine's system of axiomatic set theory, New Foundations (NF), takes its name from the title ("New Foundations for Mathematical Logic") of the 1937 article that introduced it. In the NF axiomatic system, the axiom of choice can be disproved.[36]

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__titleDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__subtextDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__quote--0DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__name--0DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__company_or_position--0DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__quote--1DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__name--1DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__company_or_position--1DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__quote--2DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__name--2DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__company_or_position--2DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__quote--3DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__name--3DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#3__company_or_position--3DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__titleDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__subtextDEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--0DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--0DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--0DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--1DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--1DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--1DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--2DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--2DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--2DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--3DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--3DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--3DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--4DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--4DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--4DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--5DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--5DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--5DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--6DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--6DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--6DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__quote--7DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__name--7DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

$_$_$DEEZ_NUTS#2__company_or_position--7DEEZ_NUTS$_$_$

The negation of the : There is a set that can be partitioned into strictly more equivalence classes than the original set has elements, and a function whose domain is strictly smaller than its range. In fact, this is the case in all known models.

weak partition principle

There is a function f from the real numbers to the real numbers such that f is not continuous at a, but f is at a, i.e., for any sequence {xn} converging to a, limn f(xn)=f(a).

sequentially continuous

There is an infinite set of real numbers without a countably infinite subset.

The real numbers are a countable union of countable sets. This does not imply that the real numbers are countable: As pointed out above, to show that a countable union of countable sets is itself countable requires the Axiom of countable choice.

[37]

There is a field with no algebraic closure.

In all models of ZF¬C there is a vector space with no basis.

There is a vector space with two bases of different cardinalities.

There is a free on countably many generators.[38]

complete Boolean algebra

There is .

a set that cannot be linearly ordered

There exists a model of ZF¬C in which every set in Rn is . Thus it is possible to exclude counterintuitive results like the Banach–Tarski paradox which are provable in ZFC. Furthermore, this is possible whilst assuming the Axiom of dependent choice, which is weaker than AC but sufficient to develop most of real analysis.

measurable

In all models of ZF¬C, the does not hold.

generalized continuum hypothesis

There are models of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory in which the axiom of choice is false. We shall abbreviate "Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory plus the negation of the axiom of choice" by ZF¬C. For certain models of ZF¬C, it is possible to validate the negation of some standard ZFC theorems. As any model of ZF¬C is also a model of ZF, it is the case that for each of the following statements, there exists a model of ZF in which that statement is true.


For proofs, see Jech (2008).


Additionally, by imposing definability conditions on sets (in the sense of descriptive set theory) one can often prove restricted versions of the axiom of choice from axioms incompatible with general choice. This appears, for example, in the Moschovakis coding lemma.

(1922), "Der Begriff "definit" und die Unabhängigkeit des Auswahlaxioms", Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften: 253–257, JFM 48.0199.02

Fraenkel, Abraham

(1960). Naive Set Theory. The University Series in Undergraduate Mathematics. Princeton, NJ: van Nostrand Company. Zbl 0087.04403.

Halmos, Paul R.

(2006). Axiom of Choice. Lecture Notes in Math. 1876. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-540-30989-5.

Herrlich, Horst

Howard, Paul; (1998). Consequences of the axiom of choice. Mathematical Surveys and Monographs. Vol. 59. Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society. ISBN 9780821809778.

Rubin, Jean E.

(2008) [1973]. The axiom of choice. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-46624-8.

Jech, Thomas

(1977). "About the Axiom of Choice". In John Barwise (ed.). Handbook of Mathematical Logic.

Jech, Thomas

(1958). "The independence of various definitions of finiteness" (PDF). Fundamenta Mathematicae. 46: 1–13. doi:10.4064/fm-46-1-1-13. Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 October 2022.

Lévy, Azriel

Per Martin-Löf, "100 years of Zermelo's axiom of choice: What was the problem with it?", in Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism: What Has Become of Them?, Sten Lindström, Erik Palmgren, Krister Segerberg, and Viggo Stoltenberg-Hansen, editors (2008).  1-4020-8925-2

ISBN

(1964). Introduction to Mathematical Logic. New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold.

Mendelson, Elliott

Moore, Gregory H. (1982). Zermelo's axiom of choice, Its origins, development and influence. . ISBN 978-0-387-90670-6., available as a Dover Publications reprint, 2013, ISBN 0-486-48841-1.

Springer

(1938), "Über den Begriff einer Endlichen Menge", Comptes Rendus des Séances de la Société des Sciences et des Lettres de Varsovie, Classe III, 31 (8): 13–20

Mostowski, Andrzej

Moore, Gregory H (2013) [1982]. Zermelo's axiom of choice: Its origins, development & influence. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications.  978-0-486-48841-7.

ISBN

Jean E. Rubin: Equivalents of the axiom of choice. North Holland, 1963. Reissued by Elsevier, April 1970. ISBN 0-7204-2225-6.

Herman Rubin

Herman Rubin, Jean E. Rubin: Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II. North Holland/Elsevier, July 1985,  0-444-87708-8.

ISBN

(1993) [1919]. Introduction to mathematical philosophy. New York: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-27724-0.

Russell, Bertrand

(1996). Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-622760-4. OCLC 175294365.

Schechter, Eric

(1972) [1960]. Axiomatic set theory. Mineola, New York: Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-61630-8.

Suppes, Patrick

George Tourlakis, Lectures in Logic and Set Theory. Vol. II: Set Theory, , 2003. ISBN 0-511-06659-7

Cambridge University Press

Zermelo, Ernst (1904). (reprint). Mathematische Annalen. 59 (4): 514–16. doi:10.1007/BF01445300. S2CID 124189935.

"Beweis, dass jede Menge wohlgeordnet werden kann"

"Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I," Mathematische Annalen 65: (1908) pp. 261–81. PDF download via digizeitschriften.de

Ernst Zermelo

entry in the Springer Encyclopedia of Mathematics.

Axiom of Choice

entry at ProvenMath. Includes formal statement of the Axiom of Choice, Hausdorff's Maximal Principle, Zorn's Lemma and formal proofs of their equivalence down to the finest detail.

Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents

Archived 15 May 2021 at the Wayback Machine, based on the book by Paul Howard Archived 26 February 2021 at the Wayback Machine and Jean Rubin.

Consequences of the Axiom of Choice

entry by John Lane Bell in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

"The Axiom of Choice"