Katana VentraIP

Rational choice theory

Rational choice theory refers to a set of guidelines that help understand economic and social behaviour.[1] The theory originated in the eighteenth century and can be traced back to the political economist and philosopher Adam Smith.[2] The theory postulates that an individual will perform a cost–benefit analysis to determine whether an option is right for them.[3] Rational choice theory looks at three concepts: rational actors, self interest and the invisible hand.[4]

This article is about a theory of economics. For rational choice theory as applied to criminology, see Rational choice theory (criminology). For rational choice theory as applied to international relations, see Rationalism (international relations).

Rationality can be used as an assumption for the behaviour of individuals in a wide range of contexts outside of economics. It is also used in political science,[5] sociology,[6] and philosophy.[7]

Overview[edit]

The basic premise of rational choice theory is that the decisions made by individual actors will collectively produce aggregate social behaviour. The theory also assumes that individuals have preferences out of available choice alternatives. These preferences are assumed to be complete and transitive. Completeness refers to the individual being able to say which of the options they prefer (i.e. individual prefers A over B, B over A or are indifferent to both). Alternatively, transitivity is where the individual weakly prefers option A over B and weakly prefers option B over C, leading to the conclusion that the individual weakly prefers A over C. The rational agent will then perform their own cost–benefit analysis using a variety of criterion to perform their self-determined best choice of action.


One version of rationality is instrumental rationality, which involves achieving a goal using the most cost effective method without reflecting on the worthiness of that goal. Duncan Snidal emphasises that the goals are not restricted to self-regarding, selfish, or material interests. They also include other-regarding, altruistic, as well as normative or ideational goals.[8]


Rational choice theory does not claim to describe the choice process, but rather it helps predict the outcome and pattern of choice. It is consequently assumed that the individual is a self-interested or “homo economicus”. Here, the individual comes to a decision that optimizes their preferences by balancing costs and benefits.[9]


Rational choice theory has proposed that there are two outcomes of two choices regarding human action. Firstly, the feasible region will be chosen within all the possible and related action. Second, after the preferred option has been chosen, the feasible region that has been selected was picked based on restriction of financial, legal, social, physical or emotional restrictions that the agent is facing. After that, a choice will be made based on the preference order.[10]


The concept of rationality used in rational choice theory is different from the colloquial and most philosophical use of the word. In this sense, "rational" behaviour can refer to "sensible", "predictable", or "in a thoughtful, clear-headed manner." Rational choice theory uses a much more narrow definition of rationality. At its most basic level, behavior is rational if it is reflective and consistent (across time and different choice situations). More specifically, behavior is only considered irrational if it is logically incoherent, i.e. self-contradictory.


Early neoclassical economists writing about rational choice, including William Stanley Jevons, assumed that agents make consumption choices so as to maximize their happiness, or utility. Contemporary theory bases rational choice on a set of choice axioms that need to be satisfied, and typically does not specify where the goal (preferences, desires) comes from. It mandates just a consistent ranking of the alternatives.[11]: 501  Individuals choose the best action according to their personal preferences and the constraints facing them.

– for any two alternatives ai and aj in the set, either ai is preferred to aj, or aj is preferred to ai, or the individual is indifferent between ai and aj. In other words, all pairs of alternatives can be compared with each other.

Completeness

– if alternative a1 is preferred to a2, and alternative a2 is preferred to a3, then a1 is preferred to a3.

Transitivity

Benefits[edit]

The rational choice approach allows preferences to be represented as real-valued utility functions. Economic decision making then becomes a problem of maximizing this utility function, subject to constraints (e.g. a budget). This has many advantages. It provides a compact theory that makes empirical predictions with a relatively sparse model - just a description of the agent's objectives and constraints. Furthermore, optimization theory is a well-developed field of mathematics. These two factors make rational choice models tractable compared to other approaches to choice. Most importantly, this approach is strikingly general. It has been used to analyze not only personal and household choices about traditional economic matters like consumption and savings, but also choices about education, marriage, child-bearing, migration, crime and so on, as well as business decisions about output, investment, hiring, entry, exit, etc. with varying degrees of success.


In the field of political science rational choice theory has been used to help predict human decision making and model for the future; therefore it is useful in creating effective public policy, and enables the government to develop solutions quickly and efficiently.


Despite the empirical shortcomings of rational choice theory, the flexibility and tractability of rational choice models (and the lack of equally powerful alternatives) lead to them still being widely used.[12]

(2008). Soldiers of Reason: The RAND Corporation and the Rise of the American Empire. New York: Harcourt.

Abella, Alex

(2002). Choice Theory: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford, ISBN 978-0192803030.

Allingham, Michael

Anand, P. (1993)."Foundations of Rational Choice Under Risk", Oxford: .

Oxford University Press

Amadae, S.M.(2003). Rationalizing Capitalist Democracy: The Cold War Origins of Rational Choice Liberalism, Chicago: .

University of Chicago Press

([1987] 1989). "Economic Theory and the Hypothesis of Rationality," in The New Palgrave: Utility and Probability, pp. 25-39.

Arrow, Kenneth J.

(1993). Rationality and Coordination. Cambridge University Press

Bicchieri, Cristina

(2003). “Rationality and Game Theory”, in The Handbook of Rationality, The Oxford Reference Library of Philosophy, Oxford University Press.

Bicchieri, Cristina

Cristian Maquieira, Jan 2019, Japan's Withdrawal from the International Whaling Commission: A Disaster that Could Have Been Avoided, Available at: , November 2019

[2]

(1957). "An Economic Theory of Democracy." Harper.

Downs, Anthony

Anthony Downs, 1957, An Economic Theory of Political Action in a Democracy, Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 65, No. 2, pp. 135–150

(1990). Foundations of Social Theory

Coleman, James S.

(2001), Surfing Economics, Pearson. Especially chapters 7 and 8

Dixon, Huw

(1979). Ulysses and the Sirens, Cambridge University Press.

Elster, Jon

(1989). Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences, Cambridge University Press.

Elster, Jon

(2007). Explaining Social Behavior - more Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences, Cambridge University Press.

Elster, Jon

Fernandez-Huerga (2008.) The Economic Behavior of Human Beings: The Institutionalist//Post-Keynesian Model" . vol. 42 no. 3, September.

Journal of Economic Issues

Schram, Sanford F. and Brian Caterino, eds. (2006). New York and London: New York University Press.

Making Political Science Matter: Debating Knowledge, Research, and Method.

Walsh, Vivian (1996). Rationality, Allocation, and Reproduction, Oxford. and scroll to chapter-preview links.

Description

and Edward J. Nell (1975) Rational Economic Man. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Martin Hollis

(1989) Ideology and Methodology. An unpublished lecture to Berkeley graduate students in 1989 discussing personal and collective survival strategies for non-mainstream economists.

Foley, D. K.

Foley, D.K. (1998). Introduction (chapter 1) in , Barriers and Bounds to Rationality: Essays on Economic Complexity and Dynamics in Interactive Systems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Peter S. Albin

Foley, D. K. (2003) Rationality and Ideology in Economics. lecture in the World Political Economy course at the Graduate Faculty of New School UM, New School.

Boland, L. (1982) The Foundations of Economic Method. London:

George Allen & Unwin

and Errouaki, K. (2011) Rational Econometric Man. Cheltenham: E. Elgar.

Edward J. Nell

(2005) The Social Structures of the Economy, Polity 2005

Pierre Bourdieu

Calhoun, C. et al. (1992) "Pierre Bourdieu: Critical Perspectives." University of Chicago Press.

Gary Browning, Abigail Halcli, Frank Webster, 2000, Understanding Contemporary Society: Theories of the Present, London, SAGE Publications

Grenfell, M (2011) "Bourdieu, Language and Linguistics" London, .

Continuum

Grenfell, M. (ed) (2008) "Pierre Bourdieu: Key concepts" London, Acumen Press

Herbert Gintis. Centre for the study of Governance and Society CSGS(Rational Choice and Political Behaviour: A lecture by Herbert Gintis. YouTube video. 23:57. Nov 21,2018)

Gilboa, Itzhak (2010). Rational Choice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Green, Donald P., and Justin Fox (2007). "Rational Choice Theory," in The SAGE Handbook of Social Science Methodology, edited by William Outhwaite and Stephen P. Turner. London: Sage, pp. 269–282.

Kydd, Andrew H. (2008). "Methodological Individualism and Rational Choice," The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, edited by Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 425–443.

Mas-Colell, A., M. D. Whinston, and J. R. Green (1995). Microeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Rational Choice Theory at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Rational Choice Theory - Article by John Scott

- on the use by Bruce Bueno de Mesquita of rational choice theory in political forecasting

The New Nostradamus

- NPR audio clip

To See The Future, Use The Logic Of Self-Interest