Katana VentraIP

Karl Leonhard Reinhold

Karl Leonhard Reinhold (26 October 1757 – 10 April 1823) was an Austrian philosopher who helped to popularise the work of Immanuel Kant in the late 18th century. His "elementary philosophy" (Elementarphilosophie) also influenced German idealism, notably Johann Gottlieb Fichte, as a critical system grounded in a fundamental first principle.

Karl Leonhard Reinhold

(1757-10-26)26 October 1757

10 April 1823(1823-04-10) (aged 65)

Jesuitenkollegium St. Anna (1772–1773)
Barnabitenkollegium St. Michael (1773–1778)
University of Leipzig
(1784; no degree)

Barnabitenkollegium St. Michael (1778–1783)
University of Jena (1787–1794)
University of Kiel (1794–1823)

Immanuel Kant (epistolary correspondent)[2]

Elementary philosophy (Elementarphilosophie), principle of consciousness (Satz des Bewußtseins)

He was the father of Ernst Christian Gottlieb Reinhold (1793–1855), also a philosopher.

Philosophical work[edit]

Letters on the Kantian Philosophy[edit]

As a former Catholic priest, Reinhold retained the values of Christian morality and individual dignity. The basic Christian doctrines of a transcendent God and an immortal human soul were presuppositions in his thinking. Reinhold tried to show that Kant's philosophy provided an alternative to either religious revelation or philosophical skepticism and fatalistic pantheism. But Kant's Critique of Pure Reason was a difficult and confusing book. It was not widely read and had little influence. Reinhold decided to write his comments on it in the literary journal The German Mercury. He skipped over the beginning and middle of the book and started at the end. Reinhold showed that the book was best read backwards, that is, starting with the end section. The last part of the Critique is where Kant discussed the issues of morality and their relation to the Rational Ideas of God, Free Will, and life after death. These issues were Reinhold's main concern. By presenting these concerns to the public, instead of the extremely difficult epistemology that took up most of the beginning and middle of the book, Reinhold aroused great interest. As a result, Kant's Critique immediately became a book of great importance.


According to historian of philosophy Karl Ameriks, "Fichte, Hegel, Schelling, Schiller, Hölderlin, Novalis, and Friedrich Schlegel all developed their thought in reaction to Reinhold's reading of Kant..."[8] There is a Faustian tendency in Reinhold's assertion that a person can hope for a future reward only because that person is constantly striving to be good. It is not moral to be good merely in the hope of reward. Reinhold's emphasis on history is evident in his declaration that philosophies and religions are to be judged on the way that they respond to the needs of reason in a particular era. Philosophical development, to him, has an underlying rationality. New philosophies are fated to struggle repeatedly in order to survive in a dialectic of history in which progress is unconsciously occurring. With regard to a transcendent God, the human internal moral law is externalized in such a deity. This extreme otherness or alienation is part of a rational process. It makes possible a subsequent deeper regaining of the self through something other than the self.

Establishing Kant on secure ground[edit]

Kant's critical philosophy was not being accepted as the final truth. According to Professor George di Giovanni, of McGill University, Reinhold tried to provide a foundation for Kant's philosophy in order to remedy this situation. Reinhold distinguished two levels of philosophy. The most basic level was the concern with consciousness and the representations that occurred in it. The second, less basic, level, was the concern with the possibility and structure of the known or desired objects.


Kant's important realization was that the possibility of metaphysics can be established. This can be done only by describing what occurs when the mind is conscious of objects. Kant's weakness was in being overly concerned with the objects themselves. He remained at the second, less basic, level of philosophy. He rarely examined what occurred in consciousness, which is the basic level of philosophy. Kant did not provide a phenomenological description of consciousness. Reinhold was convinced that Kant should have identified the fundamental fact of consciousness that was essential in making cognition itself possible.


Reinhold's Essay towards a New Theory of the Human Faculty of Representation is a description of the main parts and attributes of consciousness. In writing this book, Reinhold turned his attention from the moral issues that Kant addressed in the end section of his Critique of Pure Reason to the epistemological concerns of the beginning and middle sections.

Reinhold examined the necessary conditions of representation, such as subject and object, that must exist in order for an object to be consciously present.

Essay on a New Theory of the Human Capacity for Representation, Berlin-Boston: Walter de Gruyter, 2011.  978-3110227406

ISBN

Karl Ameriks (ed.), Letters on the Kantian Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.  978-0521830232

ISBN

Aenesidemus

Karl Leonhard Reinhold, Letters on the Kantian Philosophy, edited by , translated by James Hebbeler, Cambridge University Press, 1995, ISBN 0-521-53723-1

Karl Ameriks

George di Giovanni (ed.), Karl Leonhard Reinhold and the Enlightenment, New York: , 2010, ISBN 978-90-481-3227-0

Springer

Dieter Henrich, Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism, translated, with introductions, by George di Giovanni and H.S. Harris, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1985,  0-87220-504-5 (contains pages 37 to 138, omitting pages 3 to 36, from "The Foundation of Philosophical Knowledge")

ISBN

Karianne J. Marx, The Usefulness of the Kantian Philosophy: How Karl Leonhard Reinhold’s commitment to enlightenment influenced his reception of Kant, Boston: Walter de Gruyten, 2011,  978-3-11-025935-3

ISBN

Breazeale, Dan. . In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

"Karl Leonhard Reinhold"

at the Mathematics Genealogy Project

Karl Leonhard Reinhold