Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant[a] (22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential and controversial figures in modern Western philosophy, being called the "father of modern ethics", "father of modern aesthetics" and, by bringing together rationalism and empiricism, the "father of modern philosophy".[7][8][9][10]
"Kant" redirects here. For other uses, see Kant (disambiguation).
Immanuel Kant
12 February 1804 (aged 79)
- University of Königsberg (BA; MA, 1755; PhD, 1755; PhD, 1770)
University of Königsberg
Martin Knutzen, Johann Gottfried Teske (M.A. advisor), Konrad Gottlieb Marquardt
Jakob Sigismund Beck, Johann Gottfried Herder, Karl Leonhard Reinhold (epistolary correspondent)
- Aesthetic–teleological judgments
- Analytic–synthetic distinction
- Categorical and hypothetical imperative
- Categories
- Critical philosophy
- Copernican revolution in philosophy
- Disinterested delight
- Empirical realism
- Kant's antinomies
- Kantian ethics
- Kingdom of Ends
- Nebular hypothesis
- Transcendental schema
- Theoretical vs. practical philosophy
- Transcendental idealism
- Transcendental subject
- Understanding–reason distinction
In his doctrine of transcendental idealism, Kant argued that space and time are mere "forms of intuition" that structure all experience and that the objects of experience are mere "appearances". The nature of things as they are in themselves is unknowable to us. In an attempt to counter the philosophical doctrine of skepticism, he wrote the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), his best-known work. Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal to think of the objects of experience as conforming to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition and the categories of our understanding, so that we have a priori cognition of those objects. These claims have proved especially influential in the social sciences, particularly sociology and anthropology, which regard human activities as pre-oriented by cultural norms.[11]
Kant believed that reason is the source of morality, and that aesthetics arises from a faculty of disinterested judgment. Kant's religious views were deeply connected to his moral theory. Their exact nature, however, remains in dispute. He hoped that perpetual peace could be secured through an international federation of republican states and international cooperation. His cosmopolitan reputation, however, is called into question by his promulgation of scientific racism for much of his career, although he altered his views on the subject in the last decade of his life.