Katana VentraIP

Politics (Aristotle)

Politics (Πολιτικά, Politiká) is a work of political philosophy by Aristotle, a 4th-century BC Greek philosopher.

At the end of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle declared that the inquiry into ethics necessarily leads into a discussion of politics. The two works are frequently considered to be parts of a larger treatise — or perhaps connected lectures — dealing with the "philosophy of human affairs". In Aristotle's hierarchical system of philosophy he considers politics, the study of communities, to be of higher priority than ethics, which concerns individuals.


The title of Politics literally means "the things concerning the πόλις (polis)", and is the origin of the modern English word politics. As Aristotle explains, this is understood by him to be a study of how people should best live together in communities — the polis being seen by him as the best and most natural community for humans.


The history of Greek city-states, their wars and intrigues and political churning, was well-documented. In addition to such documentation, Aristotle pursued a research project of collecting 158 constitutions of various city-states in order to examine them for their strong and weak points. This evidence-based, descriptive approach to the study of politics was a hallmark of Aristotle's method, and a contrast with the more idealistic from-first-principles approach of Plato, as seen for example in the Republic.


As with the Nicomachean Ethics, the Politics is not a polished work as Aristotle would have written it for publication. There are various theories about the text which has come down to us. It may have been assembled from a set of shorter works on certain political themes, combined with or interlaced with his marginal notes or with the notes taken by those who attended his Lyceum lectures.

Political context[edit]

Aristotle was Macedonian. He attended Plato's Academy in Athens for about twenty years. He returned to Macedonia for a while, in part to tutor a young Alexander the Great, and then went back to Athens to found his own school, the Lycaeum. Though he spent most of his life and career in Athens, he was never an Athenian citizen, but more of a resident alien, with few political rights (he could not own property, for instance). Indeed, throughout his life, he was never a fully-fledged citizen of any Greek polis.


Citizenship in Greek city-states was usually limited to a minority of adult males. It included more responsibilities than the more passive matter-of-fact citizenship that is typical today. And it usually assumed that those who were citizens shared common goals, a common outlook, and a mutual interest in the success of the polis.


Greece was divided politically into territories ruled by many independent city-states. These often formed alliances and sometimes centrally-governed confederations (particularly in times of war). Some developed colonies, both as ways of finding new agricultural land and as ways of giving a restive underclass something to do at some distance from the ruling class.


There is a reference in the Politics to the assassination of Philip II of Macedon, which happened in 336 BC. So we know that at least some of the work was composed after the expansion of the Macedonian kingdom under Philip II which resulted in its dominion over Athens and much of the rest of Greece, subordinating Greece's many city-states to a foreign empire.


As a Macedonian and tutor to Alexander the Great, Aristotle was well-placed to be in the good graces of the political leadership of his time, until Athens challenged Macedonian power towards the end of Aristotle's life, and he went into exile from Athens to avoid the possibility of being attacked by anti-Macedonian Athenians.

Overview[edit]

Structure[edit]

Aristotle's Politics is divided into eight books, which are each further divided into chapters. Citations of this work, as with the rest of the works of Aristotle, are often made by referring to the Bekker section numbers. Politics spans the Bekker sections 1252a to 1342b.

Book I[edit]

In the first book, Aristotle discusses the city (πόλις, polis) or "political community" (κοινωνία πολιτική, koinōnía politikē) in comparison with other types of communities and partnerships such as the household (οἶκος, oikos), the master/slave relationship, and the village.


The highest form of community is the polis. Aristotle comes to this conclusion because he believes the public life is far more virtuous than the private and because "man is by nature a political animal".[1]: I.2 (1253a) [2] He begins with the relationship between the city and man,[1]: I.1–2  and then specifically discusses the household.[1]: I.3–13 [3]: 27 


He takes issue with the view that political rule, kingly rule, and rule over a household or village are only different in size, but rule over slaves was a different kind of rule. He then examines in what way the city may be said to be natural. He concludes that "the state is a creation of nature"[1]: I.2 (1253a) :

Composition[edit]

The literary character of the Politics is subject to some dispute, growing out of the textual difficulties that attended the loss of Aristotle's works. Book III ends with a sentence that is repeated almost verbatim at the start of Book VII, while the intervening Books IV–VI seem to have different flavor from the rest; Book IV seems to refer several times back to the discussion of the best regime contained in Books VII–VIII.[3]: 15  Some editors have therefore inserted Books VII–VIII after Book III. At the same time, however, references to the "discourses on politics" that occur in the Nicomachean Ethics suggest that the treatise as a whole ought to conclude with the discussion of education that occurs in Book VIII of the Politics, although it is not certain that Aristotle is referring to the Politics here.[3]: 19, 246 n. 53 


Werner Jaeger suggested that the Politics actually represents the conflation of two, distinct treatises.[5] The first (Books I–III, VII–VIII) would represent a less mature work from when Aristotle had not yet fully broken from Plato, and consequently show a greater emphasis on the best regime. The second (Books IV–VI) would be more empirically minded, and thus belong to a later stage of development.


Carnes Lord, a scholar on Aristotle, has argued against the sufficiency of this view, however, noting the numerous cross-references between Jaeger's supposedly separate works and questioning the difference in tone that Jaeger saw between them. For example, Book IV explicitly notes the utility of examining actual regimes (Jaeger's "empirical" focus) in determining the best regime (Jaeger's "Platonic" focus). Instead, Lord suggests that the Politics is indeed a finished treatise, and that Books VII and VIII do belong in between Books III and IV; he attributes their current ordering to a merely mechanical transcription error.[3]: 15–16 


It is uncertain whether Politics was translated into Arabic like most of his major works.[6]: 147, 156  Its influence and ideas were, however, carried over to Arabic philosophers.[6]: 156 

Aristotle (1948). . Translated by Barker, Sir Ernest. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

The Politics

Aristotle (1912). . Everyman's Library. Translated by Ellis, William. London: J.M. Dent & Sons.

The Politics, or a Treatise on Government

Aristotle (1885). The Politics. Translated by . Oxford: Clarendon Press. (volumes 1 and 2)

Jowett, Benjamin

Aristotle (2013). Politics. Translated by Lord, Carnes (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.  978-0-226-92183-9.

ISBN

Aristotle (1984). . Translated by Lord, Carnes. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-02669-5.

The Politics

Aristotle (1887). The Politics. Translated by Oxford: Clarendon Press. (volumes 1, 2, 3, and 4)

Newman, W.L.

Aristotle (1932). . The Loeb Classical Library. Translated by Rackham, H. London: William Heinmann.

Politics

Aristotle (1998). Politics. Translated by Indianapolis: Hackett. ISBN 978-0-87220-388-4.

Reeve, C.D.C.

Aristotle (2012). Politics. Translated by Sachs, Joe. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Focus.  978-1585103768.

ISBN

Aristotle (1997). The Politics: Translation, Analysis, and Notes. Translated by Simpson, Peter L. P. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.  978-0-8078-2327-9.

ISBN

Aristotle (1981). . Translated by Sinclair, T. A. Harmondsworth: Penguin. ISBN 978-0-14-044421-6.

The Politics

Aristotle (1894). . Translated by Susemihl, Franz; Hicks, R.D. London: MacMillan and Co.

The Politics, a Revised Text

Aristotle (1853). . Translated by Walford, Edward. London: Henry G. Bohn.

The Politics and Economics

Aristotle (1883). . Translated by Welldon, J.E.C. London: MacMillan and Co.

The Politics, with an Analysis and Critical Notes

Aristotle (1855). (ed.). The Politics, with English Notes. London: John W. Parker and Son.

Congreve, Richard

, the cycle of governments in a society

Kyklos

Plato's five regimes

(1272). Commentary on Aristotle's Politics.

Aquinas, St. Thomas

Barker, Sir Ernest (1906). . London: Methuen.

The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle

Davis, Michael (1996). The Politics of Philosophy: A Commentary on Aristotle's Politics. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

Frank, Jill (2005). A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Goodman, Lenn E.; , eds. (2007). Aristotle's Politics Today. Albany: State University of New York Press. ISBN 9780791472279.

Talisse, Robert B.

Keyt, David; Miller, Fred D. (1991). A Companion to Aristotle's Politics. Cambridge: Blackwell.

Kraut, Richard; Skultety, Steven, eds. (2005). Aristotle's Politics: Critical Essays. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

(1886). The Politics of Aristotle: Introductory Essays. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.

Lang, Andrew

Mara, Gerald (1995). "The Near Made Far Away". Political Theory. 23 (2): 280–303. :10.1177/0090591795023002005. S2CID 143561538.

doi

Mayhew, Robert (1997). . Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 0847686558.

Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Republic

Miller, Fred D. (1995). Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle's Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Nussbaum, Martha (1986). . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521277027.

The Fragility of Goodness

Salkever, Stephen, ed. (2009). Ancient Greek Political Thought. Cambridge University Press. :10.1017/CCOL9780521867535. ISBN 9780521867535.

doi

Salkever, Stephen G. (1990). . Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691078033.

Finding the Mean: Theory and Practice in Aristotelian Political Philosophy

Simpson, Peter L. (1998). . Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. ISBN 9780807823804.

A Philosophical Commentary on the Politics of Aristotle

Strauss, Leo (1964). . Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Ch. 1. ISBN 0226777014. LCCN 78-57567.

The City and Man

entry by Edward Clayton in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Aristotle: Politics

Miller, Fred. . In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

"Aristotle's Political Theory"

on In Our Time at the BBC

Aristotle's Politics

Versions