Katana VentraIP

Sovereignty

Sovereignty can generally be defined as supreme authority.[1] Sovereignty entails hierarchy within the state, as well as external autonomy for states.[2] In any state, sovereignty is assigned to the person, body or institution that has the ultimate authority over other people in order to establish a law or change existing laws.[3] In political theory, sovereignty is a substantive term designating supreme legitimate authority over some polity.[4] In international law, sovereignty is the exercise of power by a state. De jure sovereignty refers to the legal right to do so; de facto sovereignty refers to the factual ability to do so. This can become an issue of special concern upon the failure of the usual expectation that de jure and de facto sovereignty exist at the place and time of concern, and reside within the same organization.

For other uses, see Sovereignty (disambiguation).

Etymology[edit]

The term arises from the unattested Vulgar Latin *superanus (itself a derived form of Latin super – "over") meaning "chief", "ruler".[5] Its spelling, which has varied since the word's first appearance in English in the 14th century, was influenced by the English word "reign".[6][7]

Domestic sovereignty – actual control over a state exercised by an authority organized within this state

Interdependence sovereignty – actual control of movement across the state's borders

International legal sovereignty – formal recognition by other sovereign states

– there is no other authority in the state aside from the domestic sovereign (such other authorities might be e.g. a political organization or any other external agent).[8]

Westphalian sovereignty

The concept of sovereignty has had multiple conflicting components, varying definitions, and diverse and inconsistent applications throughout history.[8][9][10][11] The current notion of state sovereignty contains four aspects: territory, population, authority and recognition.[10] According to Stephen D. Krasner, the term could also be understood in four different ways:


Often, these four aspects all appear together, but this is not necessarily the case – they are not affected by one another, and there are historical examples of states that were non-sovereign in one aspect while at the same time being sovereign in another of these aspects.[8] According to Immanuel Wallerstein, another fundamental feature of sovereignty is that it is a claim that must be recognized if it is to have any meaning:


There are two additional components of sovereignty that should be discussed, empirical sovereignty and juridical sovereignty.[13] Empirical sovereignty deals with the legitimacy of who is in control of a state and the legitimacy of how they exercise their power.[13] Tilly references an example where nobles in parts of Europe were allowed to engage in private rights and Ustages, a constitution by Catalonia recognized that right which demonstrates empirical sovereignty.[14] As David Samuel points out, this is an important aspect of a state because there has to be a designated individual or group of individuals that are acting on behalf of the people of the state.[15] Juridical sovereignty emphasizes the importance of other states recognizing the rights of a state to exercise their control freely with little interference.[13] For example, Jackson and Rosberg explain how the sovereignty and survival of African states were more largely influenced by legal recognition rather than material aid.[16] Douglass North identifies that institutions want structure and these two forms of sovereignty can be a method for developing structure.[17]


For a while, the United Nations highly valued juridical sovereignty and attempted to reinforce its principle often.[13] More recently, the United Nations is shifting away and focusing on establishing empirical sovereignty.[13] Michael Barnett notes that this is largely due to the effects of the post Cold War era because the United Nations believed that to have peaceful relations states should establish peace within their territory.[13] As a matter of fact, theorists found that during the post Cold War era many people focused on how stronger internal structures promote inter-state peace.[18] For instance, Zaum argues that many weak and impoverished countries that were affected by the Cold War were given assistance to develop their lacking sovereignty through this sub-concept of "empirical statehood".[19]

History[edit]

Classical[edit]

The Roman jurist Ulpian observed that:[20]

is the transfer of territory from one state to another usually by means of treaty;

Cession

is the acquisition of territory that belongs to no state (or terra nullius);

Occupation

is the effective control of territory of another acquiescing state;

Prescription

is the acquisition of territory through natural processes like river accretion or volcanism;

Operations of nature

Creation is the process by which new land is (re)claimed from the sea such as in the Netherlands.

and

Adjudication

Conquest

A number of modes for acquisition of sovereignty are presently or have historically been recognized in international law as lawful methods by which a state may acquire sovereignty over external territory. The classification of these modes originally derived from Roman property law and from the 15th and 16th century with the development of international law. The modes are:[68]

Justifications[edit]

There exist vastly differing views on the moral basis of sovereignty. A fundamental polarity is between theories which assert that sovereignty is vested directly in the sovereigns by divine or natural right, and theories which assert it originates from the people. In the latter case there is a further division into those which assert that the people effectively transfer their sovereignty to the sovereign (Hobbes), and those which assert that the people retain their sovereignty (Rousseau).[69]


During the brief period of absolute monarchies in Europe, the divine right of kings was an important competing justification for the exercise of sovereignty. The Mandate of Heaven had similar implications in China for the justification of the Emperor's rule, though it was largely replaced with discussions of Western-style sovereignty by the late 19th century.[70]


A republic is a form of government in which the people, or some significant portion of them, retain sovereignty over the government and where offices of state are not granted through heritage.[71][72] A common modern definition of a republic is a government having a head of state who is not a monarch.[73][74]


Democracy is based on the concept of popular sovereignty. In a direct democracy the public plays an active role in shaping and deciding policy. Representative democracy permits a transfer of the exercise of sovereignty from the people to a legislative body or an executive (or to some combination of the legislature, executive and Judiciary). Many representative democracies provide limited direct democracy through referendum, initiative, and recall.


Parliamentary sovereignty refers to a representative democracy where the parliament is ultimately sovereign, rather than the executive power or the judiciary.

such as John Stuart Mill consider every individual as sovereign.

Classical liberals

view sovereignty as being untouchable and as guaranteed to legitimate nation-states.

Realists

see sovereignty similarly to realists. However, rationalism states that the sovereignty of a nation-state may be violated in extreme circumstances, such as human rights abuses.

Rationalists

believe that sovereignty is outdated and an unnecessary obstacle to achieving peace, in line with their belief in a global community. In the light of the abuse of power by sovereign states such as Hitler's Germany or Stalin's Soviet Union, they argue that human beings are not necessarily protected by the state whose citizens they are and that the respect for state sovereignty on which the UN Charter is founded is an obstacle to humanitarian intervention.[75]

Internationalists

Anarchists and some deny the sovereignty of states and governments. Anarchists often argue for a specific individual kind of sovereignty, such as the Anarch as a sovereign individual. Salvador Dalí, for instance, talked of "anarcho-monarchist" (as usual for him, tongue in cheek); Antonin Artaud of Heliogabalus: Or, The Crowned Anarchist; Max Stirner of The Ego and Its Own; Georges Bataille and Jacques Derrida talked of a kind of "antisovereignty". Therefore, anarchists join a classical conception of the individual as sovereign of himself, which forms the basis of political consciousness. The unified consciousness is sovereignty over one's own body, as Nietzsche demonstrated (see also Pierre Klossowski's book on Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle). See also sovereignty of the individual and self-ownership.

libertarians

hold a view of sovereignty where power rightfully exists with those states that hold the greatest ability to impose the will of said state, by force or threat of force, over the populace of other states with weaker military or political will. They effectively deny the sovereignty of the individual in deference to either the good of the whole or to divine right.

Imperialists

According to Matteo Laruffa "sovereignty resides in every public action and policy as the exercise of executive powers by institutions open to the participation of citizens to the decision-making processes"[76]

Air sovereignty

Autonomous area

Basileus

Mandate of Heaven

National sovereignty

Plenary authority

Self-ownership

Self-sovereign identity

Sovereignty of the individual

Souverainism

Suzerainty

Benton, Lauren (2010). . Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-88105-0.

A Search for Sovereignty: Law and Geography in European Empires, 1400–1900

Grimm, Dieter (2015). Howard, Dick (ed.). Sovereignty: The Origin and Future of a Political and Legal Concept. Columbia Studies in Political Thought / Political History. Translated by Cooper, Belinda (e-book ed.). Columbia University Press.  9780231539302.

ISBN

Paris, R. (2020). " International Organization

The Right to Dominate: How Old Ideas About Sovereignty Pose New Challenges for World Order."

Philpott, Dan (2016). . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

"Sovereignty"

(2007). Sovereignties: contemporary theory and practice. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire New York, N.Y: Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 9781403913234.

Prokhovnik, Raia

(2008). Sovereignty: history and theory. Exeter, UK Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic. ISBN 9781845401412.

Prokhovnik, Raia

Thomson, Janice E. (1996). . Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02571-1.

Mercenaries, pirates, and sovereigns: state-building and extraterritorial violence in early modern Europe

The dictionary definition of sovereignty at Wiktionary

Quotations related to Sovereignty at Wikiquote