Katana VentraIP

Ethical intuitionism

Ethical intuitionism (also called moral intuitionism) is a view or family of views in moral epistemology (and, on some definitions, metaphysics). It is foundationalism applied to moral knowledge, the thesis that some moral truths can be known non-inferentially (i.e., known without one needing to infer them from other truths one believes). Such an epistemological view is by definition committed to the existence of knowledge of moral truths; therefore, ethical intuitionism implies cognitivism.

This article is about the view in moral epistemology. For the book by Michael Huemer defending the view, see Ethical Intuitionism (book).

As a foundationalist epistemological position, ethical intuitionism contrasts with coherentist positions in moral epistemology, such as those that depend on reflective equilibrium.[1]


Despite the name "ethical intuitionism", ethical intuitionists need not (though often do) accept that intuitions of value (or of evaluative facts) form the foundation of ethical knowledge; the common commitment of ethical intuitionists is to a non-inferential foundation for ethical knowledge, regardless of whether such a non-inferential foundation consists in intuitions as such.[2]


Throughout the philosophical literature, the term "ethical intuitionism" is frequently used with significant variation in its sense. This article's focus on foundationalism reflects the core commitments of contemporary self-identified ethical intuitionists.[3][4]


Sufficiently broadly defined, ethical intuitionism can be taken to encompass cognitivist forms of moral sense theory.[5] It is usually furthermore taken as essential to ethical intuitionism that there be self-evident or a priori moral knowledge; this counts against considering moral sense theory to be a species of intuitionism. (see the Rational intuition versus moral sense section of this article for further discussion).

History[edit]

Early intuitionism[edit]

While there were ethical intuitionists in a broad sense at least as far back as Thomas Aquinas, the philosophical school usually labelled as ethical intuitionism developed in Britain in the 17th and 18th centuries.[6] Early intuitionists like John Balguy, Ralph Cudworth, and Samuel Clarke were principally concerned with defending moral objectivism against the theories of Thomas Hobbes.[7] Later, their views would be revived and developed by Richard Price and pitted against the moral sense theory of Francis Hutcheson,[8] himself sometimes considered a sentimentalist intuitionist.[9] Immanuel Kant's moral philosophy would be received in Britain as a German analog to Price,[10] though according to R. M. Hare it is questionable whether Kant is an intuitionist.[11]

Henry Sidgwick[edit]

In the 19th century, ethical intuitionism was considered by most British philosophers to be a philosophical rival of utilitarianism, until Henry Sidgwick showed there to be several logically distinct theories, both normative and epistemological, sharing the same label.[12] For Sidgwick, intuitionism is about intuitive, i.e. non-inferential, knowledge of moral principles, which are self-evident to the knower.[13] The criteria for this type of knowledge include that they are expressed in clear terms, that the different principles are mutually consistent with each other and that there is expert consensus on them. According to Sidgwick, commonsense moral principles fail to pass this test, but there are some more abstract principles that pass it, like that "what is right for me must be right for all persons in precisely similar circumstances" or that "one should be equally concerned with all temporal parts of one’s life".[14][13] The most general principles arrived at this way are all compatible with utilitarianism, which is why Sidgwick sees a harmony between intuitionism and utilitarianism.[15] There are also less general intuitive principles, like the duty to keep one's promises or to be just, but these principles are not universal and there are cases where different duties stand in conflict with each other. Sidgwick suggests that we resolve such conflicts in a utilitarian fashion by considering the consequences of the conflicting actions.[16][13] Inspired by Sidgwick, 20th century philosopher C.D. Broad would coin the term "deontological ethics" to refer to the normative doctrines associated with intuitionism, leaving the phrase "ethical intuitionism" free to refer to the epistemological doctrines.[17]

Intuitionism in analytic philosophy[edit]

Ethical intuitionism was popular in the early twentieth century, particularly among British analytic philosophers. H.A. Prichard gave a defense of the view in his "Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?" (1912), wherein he contended that moral philosophy rested chiefly on the desire to provide arguments starting from non-normative premises for the principles of obligation that we pre-philosophically accept, such as the principle that one ought to keep one's promises or that one ought not to steal.[18] This is a mistake, Prichard argued, both because it is impossible to derive any statement about what one ought to do from statements not concerning obligation (even statements about what is good), and because there is no need to do so since common sense principles of moral obligation are self-evident.


Prichard was influenced by G.E. Moore, whose Principia Ethica (1903) argued famously that goodness was an indefinable, non-natural property of which we had intuitive awareness. Moore originated the term "the naturalistic fallacy" to refer to the (alleged) error of confusing goodness with some natural property, and he deployed the Open Question Argument to show why this was an error. Unlike Prichard, Moore thought that one could derive principles of obligation from propositions about what is good.


W. D. Ross's intuitionism was influenced both by Prichard and Moore. He holds that we can know moral truths through intuition, for example, that it is wrong to lie or that knowledge is intrinsically good.[19] Intuitions involve a direct apprehension that is not mediated by inferences or deductions: they are self-evident and therefore not in need of any additional proof.[20] This ability is not inborn but has to be developed on the way to reaching mental maturity.[21] But in its fully developed form, we can know moral truths just as well as we can know mathematical truths like the axioms of geometry or arithmetic.[22][14] This self-evident knowledge is limited to general principles: we can come to know the prima facie duties this way, e.g. that, generally speaking, one should keep one's promises and refrain from harming others.[20] But intuition is unable to reveal one's absolute duty in a particular situation: what one should do all things considered.[23] All we can do is consult perception to determine which prima facie duty has the highest normative weight in this particular case, even though this usually does not amount to knowledge proper due to the complexity involved in most specific cases.[19]


Ethical intuitionism suffered a dramatic fall from favor by the middle of the century, due in part to the influence of logical positivism, in part to the rising popularity of naturalism in philosophy, and in part to philosophical objections based on the phenomenon of widespread moral disagreement. C. L. Stevenson's emotivism would prove especially attractive to Moorean intuitionists seeking to avoid ethical naturalism.[24] In the later parts of the 20th century, intuitionism would have few adherents to speak of; in Bernard Williams' words: "This model of intuition in ethics has been demolished by a succession of critics, and the ruins of it that remain above ground are not impressive enough to invite much history of what happened to it."[25]

Contemporary developments[edit]

Some recent work suggests the view may be enjoying a resurgence of interest in academic philosophy. Robert Audi is one of the main contemporary supporters of ethical intuitionism. His 2005 book The Good in the Right claims to update and strengthen Rossian intuitionism and to develop the epistemology of ethics. Michael Huemer's book Ethical Intuitionism (2005)[26] also provides a recent defense of the view. Furthermore, authors writing on normative ethics often accept methodological intuitionism as they present allegedly obvious or intuitive examples or thought experiments as support for their theories.

Audi, Robert (2004). The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton University Press.  9780691114347.

ISBN

Borchert, Donald (2006). "Sidgwick, Henry". . Macmillan.

Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition

Brink, David O. (1989). Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge University Press.  9780511624612.

ISBN

Cowan, Robert (December 2015). (PDF). European Journal of Philosophy. 23 (4): 1097–1116. doi:10.1111/ejop.12031.

"Clarifying Ethical Intuitionism"

Craig, Edward (1996b). "Sidgwick, Henry". . Routledge.

Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Craig, Edward (1996). "Ross, William David". . Routledge.

Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

(2013). "Ethics in the Analytic Tradition". In Roger Crisp (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics. Oxford University Press.

Deigh, John

(27 April 2021). "'Let no‑one ignorant of geometry…': Mathematical parallels for understanding the objectivity of ethics". Journal of Value Inquiry. 57 (published 2023): 365–384. doi:10.1007/s10790-021-09831-z. Retrieved 30 June 2021.

Franklin, James

Hare, R.M (1997). Sorting Out Ethics. Oxford University Press.  9780198250326.

ISBN

Honderich, Ted (2005). "Sidgwick, Henry". . Oxford University Press.

The Oxford Companion to Philosophy

Huemer, Michael (2005). . Palgrave Macmillan.

Ethical Intuitionism

Lewis, C.S. (1943). . MacMillan Publishing Company.

The Abolition of Man

Louden, Robert B (1996). "Toward a Genealogy of 'Deontology'". Journal of the History of Philosophy. 34 (4). Johns Hopkins University Press.

Mackie, J.L. (1977). . Penguin.

Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong

Moore, G.E. (1993). Principia Ethica (revised ed.). Cambridge University Press.

Prichard, H.A. (1912). . Mind. 21.

"Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?"

Ross, W. D. (2002) [1930]. . Clarendon Press., s.a. The Right and the Good on WP

The Right and the Good

Shafer-Landau, Russ; Cuneo, Terence, eds. (2012). Foundations of Ethics: An Anthology. Blackwell Publishing.

Sidgwick, Henry (1907). The Methods of Ethics. Macmillan.

Sidgwick, Henry (1931). Outlines of the History of Ethics (6th (enlarged) ed.). Macmillan.

Simpson, David L. . Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 12 January 2021.

"William David Ross"

Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (17 August 2006a). . In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

"Moral Skepticism"

Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2006). Moral Skepticisms. Oxford University Press.

Skelton, Anthony (2012). . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 12 January 2021.

"William David Ross"

Stratton-Lake, Philip (2013). "Rational Intuitionism". In Roger Crisp (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics. Oxford University Press.

Stratton-Lake, Philip (2014). E. Zalta (ed.). . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

"Intuitionism in Ethics"

Sturgeon, Nicholas (2002). "Ethical Intuitionism and Ethical Naturalism". Ethical Intuitionism: Re-evaluations. Oxford University Press.

Williams, Bernard (2011). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Routledge Classics.  0415610141.

ISBN

at PhilPapers

Ethical intuitionism

at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Intuitionism in Ethics

at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

A Priorism in Moral Epistemology

a contemporary defense of the theory by Michael Huemer.

Ethical Intuitionism

– by Michael Huemer.

Papers defending intuitionism