Katana VentraIP

Just war theory

The just war theory (Latin: bellum iustum)[1][2] is a doctrine, also referred to as a tradition, of military ethics that aims to ensure that a war is morally justifiable through a series of criteria, all of which must be met for a war to be considered just. It has been studied by military leaders, theologians, ethicists and policymakers. The criteria are split into two groups: jus ad bellum ("right to go to war") and jus in bello ("right conduct in war"). The first group of criteria concerns the morality of going to war, and the second group of criteria concerns the moral conduct within war.[3] There have been calls for the inclusion of a third category of just war theory (jus post bellum) dealing with the morality of post-war settlement and reconstruction. The just war theory postulates the belief that war, while it is terrible but less so with the right conduct, is not always the worst option. Important responsibilities, undesirable outcomes, or preventable atrocities may justify war.[3]

"Just war" redirects here. For the 1996 science fiction novel, see Just War (novel).

Opponents of the just war theory may either be inclined to a stricter pacifist standard (proposing that there has never been nor can there ever be a justifiable basis for war) or they may be inclined toward a more permissive nationalist standard (proposing that a war need only to serve a nation's interests to be justifiable). In many cases, philosophers state that individuals do not need to be plagued by a guilty conscience if they are required to fight. A few philosophers ennoble the virtues of the soldier while they also declare their apprehensions for war itself.[4] A few, such as Rousseau, argue for insurrection against oppressive rule.


The historical aspect, or the "just war tradition", deals with the historical body of rules or agreements that have applied in various wars across the ages. The just war tradition also considers the writings of various philosophers and lawyers through history, and examines both their philosophical visions of war's ethical limits and whether their thoughts have contributed to the body of conventions that have evolved to guide war and warfare.[5]


In the twenty-first century there has been significant debate between traditional just war theorists, who largely support the existing law of war and develop arguments to support it, and revisionists who reject many traditional assumptions, although not necessarily advocating a change in the law.[6][7]

Origins[edit]

Ancient Egypt[edit]

A 2017 study found that the just war tradition can be traced as far back as to Ancient Egypt.[8] Egyptian ethics of war usually centered on three main ideas, these including the cosmological role of Egypt, the pharaoh as a divine office and executor of the will of the gods, and the superiority of the Egyptian state and population over all other states and peoples. Egyptian political theology held that the pharaoh had the exclusive legitimacy in justly initiating a war, usually claimed to carry out the will of the gods. Senusret I, in the Twelfth Dynasty, claimed, "I was nursed to be a conqueror...his [Atum's] son and his protector, he gave me to conquer what he conquered." Later pharaohs also considered their sonship of the god Amun-Re as granting them absolute ability to declare war on the deity's behalf. Pharaohs often visited temples prior to initiating campaigns, where the pharaoh was believed to receive their commands of war from the deities. For example, Kamose claimed that "I went north because I was strong (enough) to attack the Asiatics through the command of Amon, the just of counsels." A stele erected by Thutmose III at the Temple of Amun at Karnak "provides an unequivocal statement of the pharaoh's divine mandate to wage war on his enemies." As the period of the New Kingdom progressed and Egypt heightened its territorial ambition, so did the invocation of just war aid the justification of these efforts. The universal principle of Maat, signifying order and justice, was central to the Egyptian notion of just war and its ability to guarantee Egypt virtually no limits on what it could take, do, or use to guarantee the ambitions of the state.[8]

India[edit]

The Indian Hindu epic, the Mahabharata, offers the first written discussions of a "just war" (dharma-yuddha or "righteous war"). In it, one of five ruling brothers (Pandavas) asks if the suffering caused by war can ever be justified. A long discussion then ensues between the siblings, establishing criteria like proportionality (chariots cannot attack cavalry, only other chariots; no attacking people in distress), just means (no poisoned or barbed arrows), just cause (no attacking out of rage), and fair treatment of captives and the wounded.[9]


In Sikhism, the term dharamyudh describes a war that is fought for just, righteous or religious reasons, especially in defence of one's own beliefs. Though some core tenets in the Sikh religion are understood to emphasise peace and nonviolence, especially before the 1606 execution of Guru Arjan by Mughal emperor Jahangir,[10] military force may be justified if all peaceful means to settle a conflict have been exhausted, thus resulting in a dharamyudh.[11]

East Asian[edit]

Chinese philosophy produced a massive body of work on warfare, much of it during the Zhou dynasty, especially the Warring States era. War was justified only as a last resort and only by the rightful sovereign; however, questioning the decision of the emperor concerning the necessity of a military action was not permissible. The success of a military campaign was sufficient proof that the campaign had been righteous.[12]


Japan did not develop its own doctrine of just war but between the 5th and the 7th centuries drew heavily from Chinese philosophy, and especially Confucian views. As part of the Japanese campaign to take the northeastern island Honshu, Japanese military action was portrayed as an effort to "pacify" the Emishi people, who were likened to "bandits" and "wild-hearted wolf cubs" and accused of invading Japan's frontier lands.[12]

Ancient Greece and Rome[edit]

The notion of just war in Europe originates and is developed first in ancient Greece and then in the Roman Empire.[13][14][15]


It was Aristotle who first introduced the concept and terminology to the Hellenic world that called war a last resort requiring conduct that would allow the restoration of peace. Aristotle argues that the cultivation of a military is necessary and good for the purpose of self-defense, not for conquering: "The proper object of practising military training is not in order that men may enslave those who do not deserve slavery, but in order that first they may themselves avoid becoming enslaved to others" (Politics, Book 7).[16]


In ancient Rome, a "just cause" for war might include the necessity of repelling an invasion, or retaliation for pillaging or a breach of treaty.[17] War was always potentially nefas ("wrong, forbidden"), and risked religious pollution and divine disfavor.[18] A "just war" (bellum iustum) thus required a ritualized declaration by the fetial priests.[19] More broadly, conventions of war and treaty-making were part of the ius gentium, the "law of nations", the customary moral obligations regarded as innate and universal to human beings.[20]

Christian views[edit]

Christian theory of the Just War begins around the time of Augustine of Hippo[21] The Just War theory, with some amendments, is still used by Christians today as a guide to whether or not a war can be justified. War may be necessary and right, even though it may not be good. In the case of a country that has been invaded by an occupying force, war may be the only way to restore justice. [22]

Benson, Richard. , The Tidings (2006). Showing the Catholic view in three points, including John Paul II's position concerning war.

"The Just War Theory: A Traditional Catholic Moral View"

Blattberg, Charles. . A critique of just war theory.

Taking War Seriously

Brough, Michael W., John W. Lango, Harry van der Linden, eds., Rethinking the Just War Tradition (Albany, NY: , 2007). Discusses the contemporary relevance of just war theory. Offers an annotated bibliography of current writings on just war theory.

SUNY Press

Brunsletter, D., & D. O'Driscoll, Just war thinkers from Cicero to the 21st century (Routledge, 2017).

(2002–2003). "By Any Means Necessary: Using Violence and Subversion to Change Unjust Law". UCLA Law Review. 50: 721 – via HeinOnline.

Butler, Paul

Churchman, David. "Just War Theory Across Time and Culture" in Oliver Richmond, and Gëzim Visoka, eds. The Palgrave Encyclopedia of Peace and Conflict Studies (2022)

https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77954-2_59

Churchman, David. Why we fight: the origins, nature, and management of human conflict (University Press of America, 2013) .

online

Crawford, Neta. "Just War Theory and the US Countertenor War", Perspectives on Politics 1(1), 2003.

online

Elshtain, Jean Bethke, ed. Just war theory (NYU Press, 1992) .

online

Evans, Mark (editor) Just War Theory: A Reappraisal (, 2005)

Edinburgh University Press

. War and Ethics (London, New York: Continuum, 2007). ISBN 0-8264-9260-6. A defence of an updated form of just war theory.

Fotion, Nicholas

. The Rosicrucian Philosophy in Questions and Answers – Volume II (The Philosophy of War, World War I reference, ed. 1918), ISBN 0-911274-90-1 (Describing a philosophy of war and just war concepts from the point of view of his Rosicrucian Fellowship)

Heindel, Max

Gutbrod, Hans. Assembling the Moral Puzzle – Just War Tradition and Karabakh (, February 2021); illustrates how the just war theory can offer a comprehensive assessment of the 2020 conflict around Nagorno-Karabakh.

"Global Policy Journal"

Gutbrod, Hans. Russia's Recent Invasion of Ukraine and Just War Theory (, March 2022); applies the concept to Russia's February 2022 invasion of Ukraine.

"Global Policy Journal"

Kelsay, John; Lo, PC; and Morkevicius, Valerie, McCain Conference, Stockdale Center, United States Naval Academy, 2011.

"Comparative Ethics of War: Islamic, Chinese and Hindu Perspectives,"

Khawaja, Irfan. Review of Larry May, War Crimes and Just War, in 10, ([1]), an extended critique of just war theory.

Democratiya

Lazar, Seth (Spring 2020). "War". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

MacDonald, David Roberts. Padre E. C. Crosse and 'the Devonshire Epitaph': The Astonishing Story of One Man at the Battle of the Somme (with Antecedents to Today's 'Just War' Dialogue), 2007 , South Bend. ISBN 978-1-929569-45-8

Cloverdale Books

McMahan, Jeff. "Just Cause for War," Ethics and International Affairs, 2005.

Nájera, Luna. "Myth and Prophecy in Juan Ginés de Sepúlveda's Crusading "Exhortación" 11 March 2011 at the Wayback Machine, in Bulletin for Spanish and Portuguese Historical Studies, 35:1 (2011). Discusses Sepúlveda's theories of war in relation to the war against the Ottoman Turks.

Archived

Nardin, Terry, ed. The ethics of war and peace: Religious and secular perspectives (Princeton University Press, 1998)

online

. The Just War Revisited (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).

O'Donovan, Oliver

. The Just War (New York: Scribners, 1969).

Ramsey, Paul

Steinhoff, Uwe. On the Ethics of War and Terrorism (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2007). Covers the basics and some of the most controversial current debates.

v. Starck, Christian (Ed.). Kann es heute noch gerechte Kriege geben? (Göttingen: Wallstein-Verlag, 2008).  9783835302617

ISBN

. Arguing about War, (Yale University Press, 2004). ISBN 978-0-300-10978-8

Walzer, Michael

at Catholicism.org

Catholic Teaching Concerning Just War

In Our Time, BBC Radio 4 discussion with John Keane and Niall Ferguson (3 June 1999)

"Just War"